If we posit a God beyond the God revealed, then we are left with the worst form of nominalism (I know, I just said the n-word) and skepticism. This is one of the reasons I reject Palamism. There is no such thing as a God-in-itself. Ousias do not have interiorieties.
McCormack writes,
“For Barth, the triunity of God consists in the fact that God is one Subject in three modes of being. One Subject! To say then that ‘Jesus Christ is the electing God’ is to say, ‘God determined to be God in a second mode of being.’ It lies close to hand to recognize that it is precisely the primal decision of God in election which constitutes the event in which God differentiates himself into three modes of being. Election thus has a certain logical priority even over the triunity of God. [Quoting Eberhard Jüngel:] ‘Jesus Christ is the electing God. In that here one of the three modes of being is determined to be the God who elects, we have to understand God’s primal decision as an event in the being of God which differentiates the modes of God’s being.’ So the event in which God constitutes himself as triune is identical with the event in which he chooses to be God for the human race. Thus the ‘gap’ between ‘the eternal Son’ and ‘Jesus Christ’ is overcome, the distinction between them eliminated…. There is no ‘eternal Son’ if by that is meant a mode of being in God which is not identical with Jesus Christ” (pp. 218-19).
As Ben Meyers summarizes,
The event in which God chooses to be “God for us” is identical with the event in which God “gives himself his own being.” And this event of election is not located in any timeless eternity. God’s eternal decision coincides with the temporal event in which this decision reaches its goal. This coincidence – this event of utter singularity – is God’s being. Time, then, “is not alien to the innermost being of God” (p. 222). The time of Jesus Christ is the time of God’s decision – it is the primal time, the time of God’s eternal movement into history. There is no still-more-primal divine being which lurks behind this movement into history; God’s being is this movement, this effectual decision.
Bruce McCormack suggests that the best model for understanding Karl Barth’s theology is Realdialektik–God is indirectly identical with the medium of his self-revelation. It is dialectical in the sense that it posits both a veiling and unveiling of God. God is unveiled in Jesus’s flesh, but since it is in Jesus’s flesh, God is in a sense veiled (McCormack 145). This is another way of using Luther’s Deus absconditus. Interestingly, this dialectic solves the postmodern problem of “Presence-Absence.”
What is Classical Metaphysics?
Barth’s project is in many ways an attempt to overcome the limitations of classical metaphysics. Among other things, classical metaphysics (and it doesn’t matter whether you have in mind Eastern and Western models) saw the essence of God as an abstract something behind all of God’s acts and relations (140). This view is particularly susceptible to Heidegger’s critique of “Being.” It is also susceptible, particularly in its Cappadocian form, to Tillich’s critique:
The Cappadocian “Solution” and Further Problem
According to the Cappadocians, the Father is both the ground of divinity and a particular hypostasis of that divinity. Taken together, we can now speak of a quaternity. Secondly, the distinctions between the relations are empty of content. What do the words “unbegotten,” “begotten,” and “proceeding” mean when any analogy between the divine essence and created reality is ruled illegitimate, as the Cappadocians insist (Tillich 77-78)? The Augustinian-Thomist tradition at least tried to move this forward, even if its solution was equally unsatisfactory.
Further, with regard to the Person of Christ, essentialism connotes an abstracted human nature which is acted upon (McCormack 206). Further, in essentialist forms of metaphysics the idea of a person is that which is complete in itself apart from its actions and relations (211). A wedge is now driven between essence and existence. Christologically, this means that nothing which happens in and through the human nature affects the person of the union, for the PErson is already complete anterior to these actions and relations.
Election and the Trinity
Barth navigates beyond this impasse with his now famous actualism. Rather than first positing a Trinity and then positing a decision to elect, which necessarily creates a metaphysical “gap” in the Trinity, Barth posits Jesus of Nazareth not only as the object of election (which is common to every dogmatics scheme), but also the subject of election. How can this be? How can someone be both the elector and the elected?
For Barth the Trinity is One Subject in Three Simultaneous Modes of being (218). To say that Jesus Christ is the electing God is to say that God determined to be God in a second (not being used in a temporal sense) mode of being…this lies close to the decision that [Election] constitutes an event in which God differentiates himself into three modes of being (218). Election is the event which differentiates God’s modes of being…So the event in which God is triune is identical with the event in which He chooses to be God for the human race” (ibid.)
Participation, not Theosis
Barth’s actualist ontology allows him to affirm the juridicalism within the Scriptures (which is markedly absent from many Eastern treatises) and the language of participating in the divine but without recourse to the theosis views so dependent on classical metaphysics.
Barth is historically-oriented, not metaphysically. The divine does not metaphysically indwell the human so as to heal the potential loss of being. Rather, the exaltation occurs in the history of Jesus Christ. “The link which joins the human and divine is not an abstract concept of being, but history” (230).
For Barth, God’s ontology is the act of determining to enter human history (238). God’s essence and human essence can be placed in motion–they can be actualized in history.
Exaltation, not indwelling
The terms describing Jesus’s history are agreement, service, obedience–they speak of the man Jesus standing before God, not being indwelt.
Reworking the Categories
If Barth’s criticisms of classical ontology hold, then a humble reworking of some categories is in order. Instead of hypostasis, Barth uses the term “identification.” The identification in question is an act of love. Jesus is God, but God as self-differentiation.
Would it follow, from your summary of Barth, that had God created a different world with different creatures, that he could have manifested himself very differently than trinity?
ReplyDeleteThat might be a consequence (I really don't know) but I don't think Barth would understand the question. Barthians as a whole have resisted any mention of possible-world theories.
DeleteIt seems like that would very likely be a consequence. Rather than circumnavigating the "God behind God" view, its sail seems to be made from the same material, just different rigging.
DeletePerhaps, but the reason Barthians are reticent to answer the question is that God's decision to elect cannot be abstracted from the identity of God.
DeleteI think I see, now. I'm not sure there's any payback with God's identity depending upon his relationship with the created order. Perhaps having Jesus as the object and subject of election provides a buffer...I'm just not convinced.
DeleteMoving away from abstracted identity is good, though.
This might help, and your comments prompted me to write more on this elsewhere. Barth wasn't a Hegelian, but he did retain Hegelian language (which every major thinker, conservative or liberal, from Ireland to Russia, did). Hegelian language is necessarily triadic. If you apply that to the being of God, it remains triadic.
DeleteIt's an interseting thought worth exploring.